Utilitarianism
Some Terminology
Consequentialist: According to consequentialist theories, the normative
status of an action or practice is determined solely by the consequences of the
action or practice in question.
Deontological:
According to deontological theories the normative status of
an action or practice may depend upon some features other than their
consequences. On these accounts, the concept of duty
is, in some sense, independent of the concept of good.
Hedonism: The
doctrine that pleasure and pleasure alone is good.
Utility
counted in hedons and negative hedons is pleasure - pain.
Notice that the beauty part of talking about utility rather than some other
good is that it is a common coin:
it is precisely because different people have different preferences that
we need to talk about utility.
The
Principle of Utility (PU)
: An act is right iff there is no other action that the
agent could have done which has higher utility that it has. (i.e. iff it
"maximizes utility.")
Act
Utilitarianism (AU) as we shall understand it, or "classic" act
utilitarianism, is the doctrine that the Principle of Utility (stated above) is
the criterion for morality.
Some Objections to AU Classic
Doctrine
of the Swine Objection: Pig Heaven
isn't good enough: even if we could bring about at state in which everyone was
happy as a pig in swill it would not be right to bring it about at the expense
of higher pleasures.
No
Time Objection: If we had to
calculate utility every time we acted we wouldn't be doing anything but
calculating utilities!
Trivial
Actions Objection: Where trivial
amounts of utility are at stake, it really doesn't matter whether you maximize.
Failing to maximise in such situations could hardly be wrong.
Supererogatory
Actions: On the utilitarians
account, whatever is permitted is mandatory (except where more than one action
produces maximal utility) so no action can be supererogatory, i.e. "over
and above the call of duty." Clearly, however, some actions are and this
poses a problem for the Utilitarian.
Self-Regarding
Actions Objection: On the Utilitarian account, we have the obligation,
all other things being equal, to maximize our own utility. My intuition is that
we have no obligation to be good to ourselves.
Intentions
Count Objection: On the Utilitarian account, only the consequences
of an action count when assessing its normative status: the beliefs and
intentions of the agent do not count at all. Surely this is counterintuitive.
Promise
to the Dead Man Objection: There are some conceivable
circumstances in which breaking a promise would produce higher overall utility
than keeping it (if, e.g. one has made a promise to a person who subsequently
dies, on a desert island where breaking one's promise will not set a bad
example for anyone else, etc.). In some such cases it would seem that we are
still morally obliged to keep our promise, contrary to what the utilitarian
must hold.
Response: This may be a decisive objection. Notice, that for it
to be decisive against consequentialism it is not necessary to show that
promises ought always to be kept regardless of the consequences but only
that there is at least one case where maximizing utility would not be right
because it would be promise breaking.
Punish
the Innocent Objection: In some cases, scapegoating an innocent
victim may maximize utility and thus be, on the utilitarian account, the right
thing to do. For most people this is counterintuitive.
Response:
This may also be decisive.
Stepford
Wives Objection: On the Utilitarian account it would seem that there
is nothing particularly objectionable about a world of happy, lobotomized
zombies and, if bringing about this state of affairs maximizes utility we
should go for it--even at the cost of obliterating individual autonomy.
Many
Vessels Objection: (1) Maximizing utility is not
sufficient for rightness: consider big utility pie, inequitably divided. (1) Maximizing utility is not necessary
for rightness: consider slightly smaller equitably divided utility pie.
The
fundamental problem is that without some account of distributive justice,
the utilitarian treats people (and other sentient beings) as mere vessels for
holding utility. Intuitively however the distribution matters.
Rule Utilitarianism: An Alternative to AU
Act
Utilitarianism, as we saw, makes it difficult to account for our intuitions
concerning truth-telling, promise-keeping and, in general, basic honesty. Maybe
we can live with this; maybe we can't. If we can't, then one "patch"
for utilitarianism is to reject act utilitarianism, the doctrine that
what we weigh in calculating utilities are the consequences of token actions,
in favor of some version of rule utilitarianism, according to which the
normative status of token actions is determined by their conformity to rules
or codes of conduct which are in turn assessed according to the utility
their adoption would produce.
Many
different formulations of rule utilitarianism have been proposed. The common
feature of such accounts however is the suggestion that the normative status of
token actions is not determined directly by its consequences but rather by its
conformity (or non-conformity) to some moral rule or code which is in turn
assessed with respect to its consequences.[1] Thus, schematically, rule utilitarian theories look
like this:
An act is right iff it is permitted by a correct moral rule or code.
A moral rule or code is correct iff _____
The
difference between various versions of rule utilitarianism concerns conditions
for the correctness of moral rules or codes, that is, the way in which we fill
in the blank in the above schema. The version of rule utilitarianism we shall
consider stipulates that a correct moral rule or code is one that has higher
"currency utility" than any alternative rule or code that could be
adopted.
The
Problem of Extensional Equivalence
Before
formulating this version of rule utilitarianism, one caveat for any proposed
utilitarian theory: in formulating
a rule utilitarian theory it is crucial that we avoid having it turn out to be extensionally
equivalent to act utilitarianism. To say that two moral theories are
extensionally equivalient is to say that they assign exactly the same normative
status to any action: whatever is right (wrong, obligatory, etc.) according to
one is likewise right (wrong, obligatory, etc.) according to the other. In
otherwords the two theories are, in a sense, really just saying the same thing.
Why is it so crucial to avoid formulating rule utilitarianism in such a way
that it turns out to be extensionally equivalent to act utilitarianism?
Because, silly, it would be pointless! The whole purpose of the move
from act utilitarianism to rule utilitarianism is to avoid some of the problem
cases where act utilitarianism seems to assign an intuitively incorrect
normative status to various actions--punishing the innocent, certain cases of
promise-breaking, etc. A rule utilitarian theory that is extensionally
equivalent to act utilitarianism will assign exactly the same incorrect
normative status to exactly the same actions, so it won't be any improvement at
all!
It
is precisely to avoid the problem of extensional equivalence that we have to
formulate rule utilitarianism in what may seem on the face of it an overly
complicated and fussy way. If we aren't fussy however Extensional Equivalence
could sneak in the back door and we could be stuck a disguised version of act
utilitarianism. As an example of how this could happen, consider the following
version of rule utilitarianism that fails through being extensionally
equivalent to act utilitarianism.
A
Crumby Version of Rule Utilitarianism[2]
In
formulating rule utilitarianism we may be tempted to fill in the blank in the
account of what constitutes the correctness of a moral rule or code as follows:
(1) A moral rule
or code is correct iff it maximizes utility.
This,
however won't do because it's not clear what it is for a rule or code to
maximize utility. Remember
"maximize utility" means "causes the maximal amount of
utility." Rules and codes as
such don't cause anything: strictly speaking it is rather the actions
which are done in accordance with them that cause things to happen.
Consequently we need to reformulate (1). We may be tempted to reformulate it as
follows:
(2) A
moral rule or code is correct iff everyone's acting in accordance with it
all the time would maximize utility.
The
problem with (2) is that it renders the resulting rule utilitarian theory
extensionally equivalent to act utilitarianism. Just think about it: the one
rule which guarantees that everyone's acting in accordance with it all the time
would maximize utility is precisely "Whatever happens, do whatever
maximizes utility!" And this gets us right back to where we started: act
utilitarianism. Consequently, if we want to avoid this, we need a more
sophisticated version of rule utilitarianism. One such might be formulated as
follows:
A
More Sophisticated Version of Rule Utilitarianism
On
this account, the correctness of a rule or code depends not upon everybody's
following it all the time, but rather upon it's having maximal "currency
utility." We examplain the notion of currency utility as follows:
A
rule or code is current in a society iff most normal adults in the
society believe that it is correct and sincerely attempt to act on it most of
the time and believe that most other people believe that it is correct and
sincerely attempt to act on it most of the time.
The
currency utility of a rule or code for a society is the amount of
utility produced by its being current in that society.
Given
this notion of currency utility we can formulate an account of the correctness
of moral rules and codes in terms of it as follows:
(3) An
moral rule or code is correct iff it has maximal currency utility.
It
can be shown that a formulation of rule utilitarianism in terms of (3) is not
extensionally equivalent to act utilitarianism. We leave it an open question
whether such a theory is satisfactory in other respects and whether it in fact
adequately accounts for our moral intuitions.
[1] In talking about the consequences of moral rules or codes here I'm being deliberately vague--rules or codes, strictly speaking, do not have consequences.
[2] This version of rule utilitarianism is unacceptable because it is extensionally equivalent to act utilitarianism. The reason why we formulate an unacceptable theory like this is to show what we have to avoid in formulating an acceptable theory and why such a theory will have to be a little fussy.